Introductory university-level calculus, linear algebra, abstract algebra, probability, statistics, and stochastic processes.
Continuity of real numbers
Get link
Facebook
X
Pinterest
Email
Other Apps
-
We know that \(\mathbb{R}\) (the set of real numbers) and \(\mathbb{Q}\) (the set of rational numbers) share similar properties. Both are fields and dense. What distinguishes real numbers from rational numbers is continuity. We prove Archimedes' principle as a consequence of the continuity of real numbers.
Definition (Upper bound, lower bound)
Let \(S\subset \mathbb{R}\) and \(\alpha \in \mathbb{R}\).
If, for all \(x\in S\), \(x \leq \alpha\), then \(\alpha\) is said to be an upper bound of \(S\).
If, for all \(x\in S\), \(x \geq \alpha\), then \(\alpha\) is said to be a lower bound of \(S\).
Example. Let \(A = \{x \mid x \leq 1, x \in \mathbb{R}\}\). Then, 2 is an upper bound of \(A\). 1.5 is another upper bound of \(A\). In fact, any number greater than or equal to 1 is an upper bound of \(A\). There are no lower bounds of \(A\). □
Example. Let \(B = \{x \mid x > \sqrt{2}, x\in\mathbb{Q}\}\). Any number less than or equal to \(\sqrt{2}\) is a lower bound of \(B\). There are no upper bounds of \(B\). □
The following lemma should be trivial.
Lemma
Let \(S\subset \mathbb{R}\) and \(a \in \mathbb{R}\).
\(a\) is not an upper bound of \(S\) if and only if \(\exists x\in S ~(x > a)\).
\(a\) is not a lower bound of \(S\) if and only if \(\exists x \in S ~(x < a)\).
Definition (Bounded above/below)
Let \(S \subset \mathbb{R}\). If \(S\) has an upper bound, then \(S\) is said to be bounded above. If \(S\) has a lower bound, then \(S\) is said to be bounded below. If \(S\) is bounded above and below, then \(S\) is said to be bounded.
That is, \(U(S)\) is the set of upper bounds of \(S\), and \(L(S)\) is the set of lower bounds of \(S\). Then
\(S\) is bounded above if and only if \(U(S) \neq \emptyset\).
\(S\) is bounded below if and only if \(L(S) \neq \emptyset\).
Definition (Supremum and infimum)
Let \(S \subset \mathbb{R}\).
If \(S\) is bounded above, the least upper bound, if it exists, is called the supremum of \(S\) and is denoted \(\sup S\).
If \(S\) is bounded below, the greatest lower bound, if it exists, is called the infimum of \(S\) and is denoted \(\inf S\).
In other words, \(\sup S = \min U(S)\) and \(\inf S = \max L(S)\).
Remark. It may be that \(\sup S \in S\) or \(\sup S \not\in S\). Same for \(\inf S\). □
Example.
If \(A = \{x \mid x \leq 1, x \in \mathbb{R}\}\), then \(\sup A = 1 \in A\).
If \(B = \{x \mid x \geq \sqrt{2}, x \in \mathbb{Q}\}\), then \(\inf B = \sqrt{2} \not\in B\). (Note that \(B\) is a subset of \(\mathbb{Q}\).)
□
In the closed interval \([a, b] = \{x \mid a \leq x \leq b, x\in\mathbb{R}\}\), \(b\) is the maximum value which is also the supremum. Similarly, \(a\) is the minimum value which is also the infimum. In general,
Lemma
If \(S\) has the maximum \(b\), then \(b = \sup S\).
If \(S\) has the minimum \(a\), then \(a = \inf S\).
On the other hand, the open interval \((a, b) = \{x \mid a < x < b, x\in\mathbb{R}\}\) has neither maximum nor minimum. Yet we can still define its supremum and infimum (namely, \(b\) and \(a\), respectively). Therefore, in a sense, supremum and infimum are a generalization of maximum and minimum.
We may redefine supremum and infimum in the following manner.
Definition (Supremum and infimum (second take))
Let \(S\subset \mathbb{R}\).
\(a \in \mathbb{R}\) is the supremum of \(S\) if the following two conditions are met:
\(\forall x\in S ~ (x \leq a)\). (i.e., \(a\) is an upper bound.)
If \(a' < a\), then \(\exists x\in S ~ (a' < x)\). (i.e., \(a\) is the least upper bound.)
\(a \in \mathbb{R}\) is the infimum of \(S\) if the following two conditions are met.
\(\forall x\in S ~ (x \geq a)\). (i.e., \(a\) is a lower bound.)
If \(a' > a\), then \(\exists x\in S ~ (a' > x)\). (i.e., \(a\) is the greatest lower bound.)
Lemma
Let \(S, T\) be subsets of \(\mathbb{R}\) such that \(T \subset S\). Then
\(\sup S \geq \sup T\).
\(\inf S \leq \inf T\).
Proof. In the following, \(U(S)\) and \(L(S)\) denote the set of upper bounds of \(S\) and the set of lower bounds of \(S\), respectively.
Suppose \(a \in U(S)\). Then for all \(x \in S\), we have \(x \leq a\). However, since \(T \subset S\), for all \(x\in T\), we have \(x \leq a\). In short, \(a\in U(S) \implies a \in U(T)\). Hence \(U(S) \subset U(T)\). Therefore, the minimum of \(U(S)\) is greater than or equal to the minimum of \(U(T)\). Thus \(\sup S \geq \sup T\). (You should examine why \(U(S)\subset U(T)\) implies \(\min U(S) \geq \min U(T)\).)
Similarly, we have \(L(S) \subset L(T)\). Hence \(\inf S \leq \inf T\).
■
\(\mathbb{R}\setminus\mathbb{Q}\) is the set of irrational numbers. Thus, if we consider \(\mathbb{Q}\) in \(\mathbb{R}\), there are many ``spaces'' filled by irrational numbers. But \(\mathbb{R}\) has no unfilled spaces. In this sense, \(\mathbb{R}\) is ``continuous.'' To see what this exactly means, consider the following example.
Example. \(S =\{x\mid x^2 < 2, x\in\mathbb{R}\}\) is a subset of \(\mathbb{R}\) with \(\sup S = \sqrt{2}\) and \(\inf S = -\sqrt{2}\). And, of course, \(\pm \sqrt{2} \in \mathbb{R}\), that is, both the supremum and infimum are members of \(\mathbb{R}\).
In contrast, if we only consider \(\mathbb{Q}\), then the supremum and infimum do not exist within \(\mathbb{Q}\). □
So, the very existence of supremum and infimum within \(\mathbb{R}\) illuminates the ``continuity'' of real numbers. Based on this observation, we adopt the following axioms as fundamental properties of real numbers.
Axiom (Continuity of real numbers)
Let \(S\subset \mathbb{R}\).
If \(S\) is bounded above, then \(\sup S \in \mathbb{R}\).
If \(S\) is bounded below, then \(\inf S \in \mathbb{R}\).
From this axiom, we can prove Archimedes' principle as a theorem.
Theorem (Archimedes' principle)
For any positive real number \(a\) and any real number \(b\), there exists a natural number \(n\) such that \(an > b\).
Suppose that there exists a positive real number \(a\) and a real number \(b\) such that, for any natural number \(n\), \(an \leq b\).
That is, for any natural number \(n\), we have \(n \leq \frac{b}{a}\). Therefore \(\mathbb{N}\) is bounded above. By the continuity axiom, the supremum of \(\mathbb{N}\) exists. Let \(s = \sup\mathbb{N}\). Since \(s-1\) is not the supremum of \(\mathbb{N}\), there exists \(m\in\mathbb{N}\) such that \(s-1 < m\). Therefore \(s < m + 1\). But \(m+1\) is a natural number that is greater than the supremum \(s\) of \(\mathbb{N}\), which is a contradiction. ■
Corollary
For any positive real number \(a\) and any real number \(b\), there exists a natural number \(n\) such that \(a > \frac{b}{n}\).
Proof. (Exercise.) ■
Example. Let \(A = \left\{\frac{1}{n}\mid n \in\mathbb{N}\right\}\). Then, \(\inf A = 0\).
In fact, for any \(n\in\mathbb{N}\), \(0 < \frac{1}{n}\) so that \(0\) is a lower bound of \(A\). Let \(a\) be an arbitrary positive real number. By the above corollary, there exists a natural number \(n\) such that \(a > \frac{1}{n}\). This implies that no positive real numbers are a lower bound of \(A\). Thus, all non-positive real numbers are lower bounds of \(A\), and 0 is the greatest lower bound. Thus, \(\inf A = 0\). □
Example. Let \(a,b\in\mathbb{R}\) be given. Suppose, for any positive real number \(\varepsilon\), \(|a - b| < \varepsilon\). Then \(a = b\).
This can be proved by contradiction.
Suppose \(a\neq b\). Then \(|a - b|\) is a positive real number so that there exists \(n\in\mathbb{N}\) such that
\[|a - b| > \frac{1}{n}.\tag{eq:abn}\]
But \(\frac{1}{n}\) is also a positive real number. Thus (eq:abn) contradicts the assumption that \(|a - b| < \varepsilon\) for any \(\varepsilon > 0\). □
Previously, we said that \(\mathbb{Q}\) had ``spaces'' only filled by irrational numbers. Yet, \(\mathbb{Q}\) is ``dense''.
Theorem (Denseness of rational numbers)
A non-empty open interval contains at least one rational number.
Proof. Consider an open interval \((a, b)\) where \(a < b\). If \(a < 0 < b\), then \((a, b)\) contains the rational number \(0\). If \(a < b < 0\), if \((-b, -a)\) contains a rational number \(r\), then \((a, b)\) contains the rational number \(-r\). Therefore it suffices to prove the case for \(0 < a < b\).
By Archimedes' principle, we can find a natural number \(n\) such that \((b-a)n > 1\). Then we have \(a + \frac{1}{n} < b\). Applying Archimedes' principle again, we can find a natural number \(m\) such that \(\frac{1}{n}m > a\). Taking the minimum such natural number \(m\), we have
Thus, the rational number \(\frac{m}{n}\) belongs to the open interval \((a, b)\). ■
Corollary
Let \(\alpha\) be any real number and \(\varepsilon\) be any positive real number. Then, there exists at least one rational number \(a\) such that \(|\alpha - a| < \varepsilon\).
Proof. Consider the open interval \((\alpha - \varepsilon, \alpha + \varepsilon)\). Since \(\varepsilon > 0\), this interval is not empty. By the above theorem, there exists a rational number \(a\) in this interval. Since \(a \in (\alpha - \varepsilon, \alpha + \varepsilon)\), we have
\[\alpha - \varepsilon < a < \alpha + \varepsilon\]
so that
\[|\alpha - a| < \varepsilon.\]
■
This result shows that any real number can be approximated by a rational number arbitrarily accurately.
Remark. We have used this property to derive the inverse of the natural logarithm, \(\exp(x)\), is equal to \(e^x\) for all \(x \in \mathbb{R}\) in \(\log\) and \(e\). □
\(\pi = 3.141592\cdots\) is an irrational number. Consider \(|\pi - a|\). \(a = 3.14\) is a rational number that does not satisfy \(|\pi - a| < 0.001\), but it does satisfy \(|\pi - a| < 0.002\).
Open sets In \(\mathbb{R}\), we have the notion of an open interval such as \((a, b) = \{x \in \mathbb{R} | a < x < b\}\). We want to extend this idea to apply to \(\mathbb{R}^n\). We also introduce the notions of bounded sets and closed sets in \(\mathbb{R}^n\). Recall that the \(\varepsilon\)-neighbor of a point \(x\in\mathbb{R}^n\) is defined as \(N_{\varepsilon}(x) = \{y \in \mathbb{R}^n | d(x, y) < \varepsilon \}\) where \(d(x,y)\) is the distance between \(x\) and \(y\). Definition (Open set) A subset \(U\) of \(\mathbb{R}^n\) is said to be an open set if the following holds: \[\forall x \in U ~ \exists \delta > 0 ~ (N_{\delta}(x) \subset U).\tag{Eq:OpenSet}\] That is, for every point in an open set \(U\), we can always find an open ball centered at that point, that is included in \(U\). See the following figure. Perhaps, it is instructive to see what is not an open set. Negating (Eq:OpenSet), we have \[\exists x \in U ~ \forall \delta > 0 ~ (N_{\delta}(x) \not
We would like to study multivariate functions (i.e., functions of many variables), continuous multivariate functions in particular. To define continuity, we need a measure of "closeness" between points. One measure of closeness is the Euclidean distance. The set \(\mathbb{R}^n\) (with \(n \in \mathbb{N}\)) with the Euclidean distance function is called a Euclidean space. This is the space where our functions of interest live. The real line is a geometric representation of \(\mathbb{R}\), the set of all real numbers. That is, each \(a \in \mathbb{R}\) is represented as the point \(a\) on the real line. The coordinate plane , or the \(x\)-\(y\) plane , is a geometric representation of \(\mathbb{R}^2\), the set of all pairs of real numbers. Each pair of real numbers \((a, b)\) is visualized as the point \((a, b)\) in the plane. Remark . Recall that \(\mathbb{R}^2 = \mathbb{R}\times\mathbb{R} = \{(x, y) | x, y \in \mathbb{R}\}\) is the Cartesian product of \(\mathbb{R}\) with i
We can use multiple integrals to compute areas and volumes of various shapes. Area of a planar region Definition (Area) Let \(D\) be a bounded closed region in \(\mathbb{R}^2\). \(D\) is said to have an area if the multiple integral of the constant function 1 over \(D\), \(\iint_Ddxdy\), exists. Its value is denoted by \(\mu(D)\): \[\mu(D) = \iint_Ddxdy.\] Example . Let us calculate the area of the disk \(D = \{(x,y)\mid x^2 + y^2 \leq a^2\}\). Using the polar coordinates, \(x = r\cos\theta, y = r\sin\theta\), \(dxdy = rdrd\theta\), and the ranges of \(r\) and \(\theta\) are \([0, a]\) and \([0, 2\pi]\), respectively. Thus, \[\begin{eqnarray*} \mu(D) &=& \iint_Ddxdy\\ &=&\int_0^a\left(\int_0^{2\pi}rd\theta\right)dr\\ &=&2\pi\int_0^a rdr\\ &=&2\pi\left[\frac{r^2}{2}\right]_0^a = \pi a^2. \end{eqnarray*}\] □ Volume of a solid figure Definition (Volume) Let \(V\) be a solid figure in the \((x,y,z)\) space \(\mathbb{R}^3\). \(V\) is sai
Comments
Post a Comment